top of page

The Freedom Within: Unlocking Emotional Awareness and Self-Discovery

Nathan Foust

Introduction

Jean-Paul Sartre, a towering figure in 20th-century philosophy, developed a profound concept of ‘being’ that remains central to existentialist thought. His exploration of existence, particularly through his work Being and Nothingness (1943), delves into the nature of human identity, freedom, and the self’s relationship with the world. Sartre’s ideas about ‘being’ offer a compelling framework for understanding not only how we perceive ourselves but also how we relate emotionally to our existence. Sartre’s concept of ‘being,’ including the differences between being-for-itself (être-pour-soi) and being-in-itself (être-en-soi), and will explore how these ideas help illuminate the development of emotional self-awareness. Sartre’s emphasis on freedom, responsibility, and the ‘look’ of the Other will be key components in understanding how emotional self-awareness emerges in the context of existential thought.


The tension between subjective experience and objective reality forms the core of Sartre’s philosophy. While modern psychology may emphasize biological and social influences on emotional self-awareness, Sartre’s existential framework challenges individuals to take full responsibility for their emotional lives. Emotions are not just reactions to external stimuli but are experienced as part of an ongoing process of self-definition. Sartre’s work encourages a deeper examination of how the awareness of freedom and the inevitable confrontation with existential anxiety shape emotional experiences. By drawing from Sartre’s ideas, we can gain insight into how individuals navigate complex emotional states such as shame, guilt, anxiety, and joy in relation to their sense of self and the world around them.


This exploration of Sartre’s notion of ‘being’ will demonstrate that emotional self-awareness cannot be fully understood without considering how individuals actively engage with their freedom and the burden of responsibility. As we proceed, we will also address key existential themes such as authenticity, bad faith, and the concept of the Other, all of which contribute to an understanding of the emotional experience from an existentialist perspective.


Question for consideration: How do Sartre’s distinctions between being-for-itself and being-in-itself inform our understanding of emotional self-awareness?



Sartre’s Concept of ‘Being’ and the Self

In Sartre’s philosophy, ‘being’ is not a static or immutable state, but rather a dynamic and fluid process. Sartre posits two fundamental types of being: being-for-itself and being-in-itself. These two forms of being delineate the difference between human consciousness and the inert world of objects. Being-in-itself refers to the being of objects or things, which simply exist without the ability to reflect, alter, or transcend their current state. For example, a rock or a tree is a being-in-itself. It simply is what it is; it has no capacity for self-awareness or transformation beyond its material properties.


In contrast, being-for-itself is the being of human consciousness, characterized by intentionality, self-awareness, and the ability to reflect upon itself. This form of being is dynamic, constantly changing, and bound to the subject’s freedom. Sartre argues that humans are unique in their capacity for being-for-itself because they can question their own existence, shape their future, and make choices that define their identity. Unlike objects, humans are aware that they are and can reflect upon their own being. This reflective consciousness is the essence of being-for-itself.


The key to Sartre’s existential philosophy lies in his claim that existence precedes essence. For Sartre, humans are not born with a predefined nature or purpose. Instead, individuals must create their own meaning and identity through their choices and actions. This concept is radically liberating but also profoundly unsettling, as it places the burden of self-definition entirely on the individual. The individual is “condemned to be free” because there are no external guidelines, morals, or purposes that can dictate how one should live. One’s essence is never fixed but must be constructed through the ongoing process of becoming. This self-creation is an essential part of emotional self-awareness, as individuals must navigate their emotions, desires, and actions while confronting the freedom to choose and the weight of responsibility.


For Sartre, emotional self-awareness arises from the recognition that one’s emotions are tied to one’s freedom. Emotions are not mere reactions to external stimuli, but active choices that reflect how individuals engage with the world and define themselves. Anxiety, joy, guilt, and other emotions are manifestations of the individual’s confrontation with freedom and the awareness of one’s existential condition. This recognition of freedom provides a deeper understanding of emotional self-awareness because it emphasizes that individuals are not passive recipients of emotion, but active participants in shaping their emotional landscape.


Moreover, Sartre introduces the concept of being-for-others—the idea that individuals are always aware that they exist in the gaze of others. While the self may reflect upon itself in isolation, the self is also always aware of being seen, judged, and defined by others. This introduces a tension between the self as a subjective being and the self as an object in the world, a tension that is central to the emotional experience.


Question for consideration: In what ways does Sartre’s concept of being-for-itself help explain the human capacity for emotional self-awareness?


The Role of the Other and the ‘Look’

One of the most significant elements in Sartre’s philosophy is the concept of the Other, which plays a pivotal role in the formation of the self. Sartre famously discusses the ‘look’ (le regard) of the Other as a defining moment in the development of human consciousness. The ‘look’ refers to the experience of being observed by another person, and it holds deep existential implications for how one perceives oneself.


When an individual becomes aware of being seen by another, they experience a profound shift in their understanding of themselves. They realize that they are no longer simply subjects, but objects in the world as perceived by the Other. The awareness of the Other’s gaze brings into focus the fact that the self is not only defined by its internal reflection but also by the way it is perceived and judged by others. In Sartre’s terms, the Other’s gaze objectifies the self, reducing it to a thing in the world.


This experience of being seen is critical for emotional self-awareness because it forces the individual to confront the fact that their identity is not solely self-determined. They are shaped by the perceptions and judgments of others. The ‘look’ introduces a sense of vulnerability, as the individual is now subject to the interpretations and expectations of the Other. Sartre’s existentialism suggests that this recognition of objectification can lead to anxiety, shame, and even alienation, as the self struggles to reconcile its internal sense of subjectivity with its external objectification.


In terms of emotional self-awareness, the experience of being seen by the Other is essential because it shapes how individuals understand their own emotions. Emotions like shame, pride, or embarrassment are intricately tied to how one perceives the judgment of others. For instance, the emotion of shame arises when an individual becomes aware that they are being perceived as inadequate, flawed, or exposed. This recognition can provoke deep existential anxiety, as the individual must confront not only their own vulnerability but also the external pressure to conform to societal norms or expectations.


However, Sartre’s theory of the Other is not purely negative. The gaze of the Other also presents an opportunity for self-reflection and self-definition. By becoming aware of the Other’s gaze, individuals can engage in a process of introspection that allows them to define who they are, independent of external judgments. Thus, emotional self-awareness involves both confronting the pain of objectification and the possibility of transcending it through authentic self-reflection.


Question for consideration: How does the experience of being seen by the Other influence emotional self-awareness and the development of the self in Sartre’s philosophy?


Emotional Self-Awareness and the Freedom of Choice

Emotional self-awareness, in Sartre’s framework, cannot be separated from the existential idea of freedom. Sartre argues that humans are condemned to be free, meaning that they must continually choose and define themselves in the face of an indifferent or even hostile world. This freedom is not simply the ability to choose between alternatives, but rather the ability to create one’s essence through those choices. This is a terrifying freedom, as it means that there are no predefined paths or external guarantees for meaning or purpose. Each individual must navigate their existence and make choices that define who they are.


The emotional experience of anxiety is deeply connected to this awareness of freedom. Sartre explains that anxiety arises not from the fear of particular objects or events, but from the recognition of one’s absolute freedom to choose and be responsible for one’s actions. This freedom can be overwhelming, as it implies that individuals are entirely responsible for their lives and their emotions. Anxiety, in Sartre’s view, is the emotional response to the realization that one’s life is contingent upon their own decisions, and there is no external authority to provide meaning or direction.


For Sartre, emotional self-awareness requires acknowledging the role of freedom in shaping emotional responses. Rather than being passive victims of circumstance, individuals are active participants in how they respond to events and relationships. Emotional self-awareness involves recognizing that emotions like guilt, fear, and shame arise from one’s own choices, rather than from external events or forces. The ability to confront these emotions and take responsibility for them is essential to authentic existence.


Furthermore, Sartre’s notion of freedom is deeply intertwined with the idea of bad faith. Bad faith refers to the tendency of individuals to deceive themselves in order to avoid confronting the full weight of their freedom. In bad faith, individuals deny their responsibility for their emotions and actions by attributing them to external factors or societal pressures. For example, a person might blame their emotional state on their upbringing, social circumstances, or the actions of others. By doing so, they avoid taking responsibility for their own emotional life. Emotional self-awareness, therefore, requires an honest confrontation with the fact that one is free to choose how to respond to their emotions.


Question for consideration: How does Sartre’s concept of freedom shape the way individuals experience and understand their emotions?


The Intersection of Authenticity and Emotional Self-Awareness

For Sartre, authenticity is a key component of existential existence. To live authentically is to embrace one’s freedom and responsibility fully, without evasion or bad faith (mauvaise foi). Bad faith refers to the self-deception that arises when an individual denies their own freedom and responsibility by adopting socially prescribed roles or identities. In contrast, authentic existence involves the honest recognition of one’s freedom to choose and to act in accordance with one’s true self, rather than conforming to external expectations.


Emotional self-awareness is deeply linked to the concept of authenticity because it requires individuals to be honest with themselves about their emotional responses and the reasons behind them. Authentic emotional experience is one that arises from the individual’s true understanding of their feelings, free from the distortions of societal pressures or internalized norms. For example, the emotion of guilt may arise in response to a violation of personal values or ethical standards, but it can also be a form of self-deception if it stems from social conditioning rather than genuine moral reflection. Authentic emotional self-awareness involves examining the roots of one’s emotions and the extent to which they reflect true desires and values.


To live authentically is to confront the full complexity of one’s emotions, including the uncomfortable or painful ones. This requires a willingness to acknowledge emotions like guilt, shame, and fear without resorting to defense mechanisms of repression or denial. Authentic emotional self-awareness is not about avoiding difficult emotions but engaging with them in a way that reflects one’s true existential condition. Authenticity also involves recognizing that emotions are not static but are always subject to change based on one’s choices and actions. In this way, emotional self-awareness allows individuals to develop a deeper understanding of themselves and their relationship to the world.


Question for consideration: In what ways does Sartre’s concept of authenticity influence the development of emotional self-awareness?


Conclusion

Sartre’s exploration of ‘being’ provides a profound framework for understanding emotional self-awareness. By distinguishing between being-for-itself and being-in-itself, Sartre offers a model for understanding the human capacity for self-reflection and emotional experience. The ‘look’ of the Other introduces a critical element of external perception, revealing the tension between the individual’s subjective experience and their objectified presence in the world. Ultimately, emotional self-awareness in Sartre’s philosophy emerges from the interplay between freedom, responsibility, and authenticity. By recognizing the inherent freedom in our emotional responses and embracing the responsibility that comes with it, individuals can cultivate a deeper and more authentic understanding of their emotional lives. Further Reading

  1. Sartre, J.-P. (1943). Being and Nothingness. Gallimard.

  2. Nagel, T. (1986). The View from Nowhere. Oxford University Press.

  3. Camus, A. (1942). The Myth of Sisyphus. Gallimard.

  4. Flynn, T. (2006). Existentialism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.

  5. Yalom, I. D. (1980). Existential Psychotherapy. Basic Books.


 
 
 

Comments


  • Instagram
  • Facebook
  • Twitter
  • YouTube

DISCLAIMER:

As with any diet, supplement, or exercise program, always consult a qualified physician prior to beginning any new routine, especially if you have any health issues. The training and information provided on this site and in person is for educational consideration only and is not intended to diagnose, treat, or cure any disease, nor is it to take the place of any qualified medical treatment.

All original material presented represents the thoughts, opinions, and experiences of the author and is intended to be taken as such. All quoted or shared material is the property and responsibility of the original author/source.

©2025 by Wholeo-Awakening.

bottom of page